Dictionary Definition
metaphysics n : the philosophical study of being
and knowing
User Contributed Dictionary
English
Etymology
From metaphysica < Byzantine Greek (metaphusika) < (meta) "after" + (phusikos) "natural". The word derives from the title of the collection by Aristotle "μετὰ τὰ φυσικά" (after the natural things).Pronunciation
- /mɛtəˈfɪzɪks/
Noun
- philosophy uncountable The branch of
philosophy which
studies fundamental
principles intended
to describe or explain all that is, and which are not themselves
explained by anything more fundamental; the study of first
principles; the study of being insofar as it is being (ens
in quantum ens).
- Philosophers sometimes say that metaphysics is the study of the ultimate furniture of the universe.
- philosophy countable The view or theory of a particular
philosopher or school of thinkers concerning the first principles
which describe or explain all that is.
- The metaphysics of Thomas Aquinas holds that all real beings
have both essence and existence.
- In Aristotelian metaphysics physical objects have both form and matter.
- In his Pensées, Pascal mentioned some first principles recognized within his metaphysics: space, time, motion, and number.
- In Aristotelian metaphysics physical objects have both form and matter.
- The metaphysics of Thomas Aquinas holds that all real beings
have both essence and existence.
- Any fundamental principles or rules.
- 1990, Lance Morrow, "Gorbachev:
The Unlikely Patron of Change," Time, 1 Jan,
- The metaphysics of global power has changed. Markets are now more valuable than territory.
- 1990, Lance Morrow, "Gorbachev:
The Unlikely Patron of Change," Time, 1 Jan,
- The study of a supersensual realm or of
phenomena which transcend the physical world.
- I have a collection of books on metaphysics, covering astral projection, reincarnation, and communication with spirits.
- Displeasingly
abstruse, complex material on any subject.
- This political polemic strikes me as a protracted piece of overwrought, fog shrouded metaphysics!
- Plural of countable senses of metaphysic.
Derived terms
Related terms
Translations
branch of philosophy that studies first
principles
- Catalan: metafísica
- Chinese: 形而上学 (xíng'érshàngxué)
- Dutch: metafysica
- Esperanto: metafiziko
- Finnish: metafysiikka
- German: Metaphysik
- Indonesian: metafisika
- Interlingua: metaphysica
- Japanese: 形而上学 (けいじじょうがく, keijijōgaku)
- Korean: 형이상학
- Latin: metaphysica
- Norwegian: metafysikk
- Polish: metafizyka
- Portuguese: metafísica
- Scots: metapheisics
- Slovene: metafizika
- Spanish: metafísica
Extensive Definition
- For Aristotle's work, see Metaphysics (Aristotle). For Avicenna's work, see Avicennism.
Metaphysics is the branch of philosophy investigating
principles of reality transcending those of any particular science.
Cosmology
and ontology are
traditional branches of metaphysics. It is concerned with
explaining the ultimate nature of being and the world.
The word derives from the Greek
words μετά (metá) (meaning "after") and φυσικά (physiká) (meaning
"physical"), "physical" referring to those works on matter by
Aristotle
in antiquity. The prefix meta- ("after") was attached to the
chapters in Aristotle's work that physically followed after the
chapters on "physics", in posthumously edited collections.
Aristotle called some of the subjects treated there "first
philosophy"
A central branch of metaphysics is ontology, the investigation
into what types of
things there are in the world and what relations these things
bear to one another. The metaphysician also attempts to clarify the
notions by which people understand the world, including existence, objecthood,
property,
space, time, causality, and possibility.
More recently, the term "metaphysics" has also
been employed by non-philosophers to refer to "subjects that are
beyond the physical world". A "metaphysical bookstore", for
instance, is not one that sells books on ontology, but rather one
that sells esoteric
books on spirits,
faith
healing, crystal
power, occultism,
and other such topics which the philosophic pursuit of metaphysics
generally does not include.
Before the development of modern
science, scientific questions were addressed as a part of
metaphysics known as "natural
philosophy"; the term "science" itself meant "knowledge". The
Scientific
Revolution, however, made natural philosophy an empirical and experimental activity unlike
the rest of philosophy, and by the end of the eighteenth
century it had begun to be called "science" in order to
distinguish it from philosophy. Thereafter, metaphysics became the
philosophical enquiry of a non-empirical character into the nature
of existence.
History of metaphysics
One of the first metaphysicians is Parmenides of Elea. He held that the multiplicity of existing things, their changing forms and motion, are but an appearance of a single eternal reality (“Being”), thus giving rise to the Parmenidean principle that “all is one.” From this concept of Being, he went on to say that all claims of change or of non-Being are illogical. Because he introduced the method of basing claims about appearances on a logical concept of Being, he is considered one of the founders of metaphysics.Metaphysics, is called "first philosophy" by
Aristotle. The
editor of his works, Andronicus
of Rhodes, is thought to have placed the books on first
philosophy right after another work, Physics, and called them (ta
meta ta physika biblia) or, "the books that come after the [books
on] physics." This was misread by Latin scholiasts,
who thought it meant "the science of what is beyond the physical."
In the English language, the word comes by way of the Medieval
Latin metaphysica, the neuter plural of Medieval
Greek metaphysika. While its Greek and Latin origins are clear,
various dictionaries trace its first appearance in English to the
mid-sixteenth century, although in some cases as early as
1387.
Aristotle's Metaphysics
was divided into three parts, in addition to some smaller sections
related to a philosophical lexicon and some reprinted extracts from
the Physics,
which are now regarded as the proper branches of traditional
Western metaphysics:
Universal science or first philosophy treats of
"being qua being" — that is, what is basic to all science
before one adds the particular details of any one science.
Essentially "being qua being"
may be translated as "being insofar as being goes", or as, "being
in terms of being". This includes topics such as causality,
substance, species and elements, as well as the notions of
relation, interaction, and finitude.
Metaphysics as a discipline was a central part
of academic inquiry and scholarly education even before the age of
Aristotle. Long
considered "the Queen of Sciences", its issues were considered no
less important than the other main formal subjects of physical
science, medicine,
mathematics,
poetics and music. Since the beginning
of modern philosophy during the seventeenth century, problems
that were not originally considered within the bounds of
metaphysics have been added to its purview, while other problems
considered metaphysical for centuries are now typically relegated
to their own separate regions in philosophy, such as philosophy
of religion, philosophy
of mind, philosophy
of perception, philosophy
of language, and philosophy
of science.
In some cases, subjects of metaphysical
scholarship have been found to be entirely physical and natural,
thus making them part of physics proper (cf. Albert
Einstein's Theory
of Relativity).
Central questions of metaphysics
Most positions that can be taken with regards to any of the following questions are endorsed by one or another notable philosopher. It is often difficult to frame the questions in a non-controversial manner.Mind and matter
The nature of matter was a problem in its own right in early philosophy. Aristotle himself introduced the idea of matter in general to the Western world, adapting the term hyle which originally meant "lumber". Early debates centered on identifying a single underlying principle. Water was claimed by Thales, Air by Anaximenes, Apeiron (the Boundless) by Anaximander, Fire by Heraclitus. Democritus conceived an atomic theory many centuries before it was accepted by modern science.The nature of the mind and its relation to the body
has been seen as more of a problem as science has progressed in its
mechanistic
understanding of the brain and body. Proposed solutions often have
ramifications about the nature of mind as a whole. René
Descartes proposed substance
dualism, a theory in which mind and body are essentially quite
different, with the mind having some of the attributes
traditionally assigned to the soul, in the seventeenth century.
This creates a conceptual puzzle about how the two interact (which
has received some strange answers, such as occasionalism). Evidence
of a close relationship between brain and mind, such as the
Phineas
Gage case, have made this form of dualism increasingly
unpopular.
Another proposal discussing the mind-body problem
is idealism, in which
the material is sweepingly eliminated in favor of the mental.
Idealists, such as George
Berkeley, claim that material objects do not exist unless
perceived and only as perceptions. The "German idealists" such as
Fichte,
Hegel and
Schopenhauer
took Kant as
their starting-point, although it is debatable how much of an
idealist Kant himself was. Idealism is also a common theme in
Eastern philosophy. Related ideas are panpsychism and panexperientialism
which say everything has a mind rather than everything exists in a
mind. Alfred
North Whitehead was a twentieth-century exponent of this
approach.
Idealism is a
monistic
theory, in which there is a single universal substance or
principles. Neutral
monism, associated in different forms with Baruch
Spinoza and Bertrand
Russell is a theory which seeks to be less extreme than
idealism, and to avoid the problems of substance
dualism. It claims that existence consists of a single
substance, which in itself is neither mental nor physical, but is
capable of mental and physical aspects or attributes –
thus it implies a dual-aspect
theory.
For the last one hundred years, the dominant
metaphysics has without a doubt been materialistic monism. Type
identity
theory, token identity
theory, functionalism, reductive
physicalism, nonreductive
physicalism, eliminative
materialism, anomalous
monism, property
dualism, epiphenomenalism and
emergence are just
some of the candidates for a scientifically-informed account of the
mind. (It should be noted that while many of these positions are
dualisms, none of them are substance dualism.)
Prominent recent philosophers of mind include
David
Armstrong, Ned Block,
David
Chalmers, Patricia
and Paul
Churchland,
Donald Davidson, Daniel
Dennett, Douglas
Hofstadter, Jerry Fodor,
David
Lewis, Thomas
Nagel, Hilary
Putnam, John Searle,
John
Smart and Ludwig
Wittgenstein.
Objects and their properties
further Problem of universals The world seems to contain many individual things, both physical, like apples, and abstract such as love and the number 3. Such objects are called particulars. Now, consider two apples. There seem to be many ways in which those two apples are similar, they may be approximately the same size, or shape, or color. They are both fruit, etc. One might also say that the two apples seem to have some thing or things in common. Universals or Properties are said to be those things.Metaphysicians concerned with questions about
universals or particulars are interested in the nature of objects
and their properties,
and the relationship between the two. For instance, one might hold
that properties are abstract objects, existing outside of space and time, to which particular objects
bear special relations. Others maintain that what particulars are
is a bundle or
collection of properties (specifically, a bundle of properties they
have).
Identity and change
The Greeks took some extreme positions on the nature of change: Parmenides denied that change occurs at all, while Heraclitus thought change was ubiquitous: "[Y]ou cannot step into the same river twice".Identity, sometimes called Numerical
Identity, is the relation that a "thing" bears to itself, and
which no "thing" bears to anything other than itself (cf. sameness). According to
Leibniz,
if some object x is identical to some object y, then any property
that x has, y will have as well. However, it seems, too, that
objects can change over time. If one were to look at a tree one
day, and the tree later lost a leaf, it would seem that one could
still be looking at that same tree. Two rival theories to account
for the
relationship between change and identity are Perdurantism,
which treats the tree as a series of tree-stages, and Endurantism
which maintains that the tree -- the same tree -- is present at
every stage in its history.
Space and time
In the Middle Ages, Saint
Augustine of Hippo asked the fundamental question about the
nature of time. A traditional realist
position in ontology is that time and space have existence apart
from the human mind. Idealists,
including Kant
claim that space and time are mental constructs used to organise
perceptions, or are otherwise unreal.
Suppose that one is sitting at a table, with an
apple in front of him or her; the apple exists in space and in time, but what does this statement
indicate? Could it be said, for example, that space is like an
invisible three-dimensional grid in which the apple is positioned?
Suppose the apple, and all physical objects in the universe, were
removed from existence entirely. Would space as an "invisible grid"
still exist? René
Descartes and Leibniz believed it
would not, arguing that without physical objects, "space" would be
meaningless because space is the framework upon which we understand
how physical objects are related to each other. Newton, on
the other hand, argued for an absolute
"container"
space. The pendulum swung back to relational
space with Einstein and
Ernst
Mach.
While the absolute/relative debate, and the
realism debate are equally applicable to time and space, time
presents some special problems of its own. The flow of time has
been denied in ancient times by Parmenides and
more recently by J. M.
E. McTaggart in his paper The
Unreality of Time.
The direction of time, also known as "time's
arrow", is also a puzzle, although physics is now driving the
debate rather than philosophy. It appears that fundamental laws are
time-reversible and the arrow of time must be an "emergent" phenomenon, perhaps
explained by a statistical understanding of thermodynamic
entropy.
Common-sense tells us that objects persist across
time, that there is some sense in which you are the same person you
were yesterday, in which the oak is the same as the acorn, in which
you perhaps even can step into the same river twice. Philosophers
have developed two rival theories for how this happens, called
"endurantism" and
"perdurantism".
Broadly speaking, endurantists hold that a whole object exists at
each moment of its history, and the same object exists at each
moment. Perdurantists believe that objects are four-dimensional
entities made up of a series of temporal
parts like the frames of a movie.
Religion and spirituality
Theology is the study of God and the Nature of the Divine. Is there a God (monotheism), many gods (polytheism) or no gods (atheism)? Is it impossible to know if any gods exist (agnosticism)? Does the Divine intervene directly in the world (theism), or is its sole function to be the first cause of the universe (deism)? Are God and the World different (panentheism, dualism) or are they identical (pantheism)? These are the primary metaphysical questions concerning theologians.Within the standard Western philosophical
tradition, theology reached its peak under the medieval school of thought
known as scholasticism, which
focused primarily on the metaphysical aspects of Christianity.
While the work of the scholastics has been largely eclipsed in the
wake of modern philosophy, key figures such as Thomas
Aquinas still play an important role in the philosophy
of religion.
Necessity and possibility
Metaphysicians investigate questions about the ways the world could have been. David Lewis, in "On the Plurality of Worlds," endorsed a view called Concrete Modal realism, according to which facts about how things could have been are made true by other concrete worlds, just like ours, in which things are different. Other philosophers, such as Gottfried Leibniz, have dealt with the idea of possible worlds as well. The idea of necessity is that any necessary fact is true across all possible worlds; that is, we could not imagine it to be otherwise. A possible fact is true in some possible world, even if not in the actual world. For example, it is possible that cats could have had two tails, or that any particular apple could have not existed. By contrast, certain propositions seem necessarily true, such as analytic propositions, e.g. "All bachelors are unmarried." The particular example of analytic truth being necessary is not universally held among philosophers. A less controversial view might be that self-identity is necessary, as it seems fundamentally incoherent to claim that for any x, it is not identical to itself; this is known as the law of identity, a putative "first principle". Aristotle describes the principle of non-contradiction, "It is impossible that the same quality should both belong and not belong to the same thing . . . This is the most certain of all principles . . . Wherefore they who demonstrate refer to this as an ultimate opinion. For it is by nature the source of all the other axioms."Abstract objects and mathematics
Some philosophers endorse views according to which there are abstract objects such as numbers, or Universals. (Universals are properties that can be instantiated by multiple objects, such as redness or squareness.) Abstract objects are generally regarded as being outside of space and time, and/or as being causally inert. Mathematical objects and fictional entities and worlds are often given as examples of abstract objects. The view that there really are no abstract objects is called nominalism. Realism about such objects is exemplified by Platonism. Other positions include moderate realism, as espoused by Aristotle, and conceptualism.The philosophy
of mathematics overlaps with metaphysics because some positions
are
realistic in the sense that they hold that mathematical objects
really exist, whether transcendentally, physically, or mentally.
Platonic
realism holds that mathematical entities are a transcendent
realm of non-physical objects. The simplest form of mathematical
empiricism claims that mathematical objects are just ordinary
physical objects, i.e. that squares and the like physically exist.
Plato
rejected this view, among other reasons, because geometrical
figures in mathematics have a perfection that no physical
instantiation can capture. Modern mathematicians have developed
many strange and complex mathematical structures with no
counterparts in observable reality, further undermining this view.
The third main form of realism holds that mathematical entities
exist in the mind. However, given a materialistic
conception of the mind, it does not have the capacity to literally
contain the many infinities of objects in mathematics. Intuitionism,
inspired by Kant, sticks with the
idea that "there are no non-experienced mathematical truths". This
involves rejecting as intuitionistically unacceptable anything that
cannot be held in the mind or explicitly constructed.
Intuitionists reject the
law of the excluded middle and are suspicious of infinity,
particularly of transfinite
numbers.
Other positions such as formalism and fictionalism
that do not attribute any existence to mathematical entities are
anti-realist.
Determinism and free will
Determinism is the philosophical proposition that every event, including human cognition, decision and action, is causally determined by an unbroken chain of prior occurrences. It holds that no random, spontaneous, mysterious, or miraculous events occur. The principal consequence of the deterministic claim is that it poses a challenge to the existence of free will.The problem of free will is
the problem of whether rational agents exercise control over their
own actions and decisions. Addressing this problem requires
understanding the relation between freedom and causation, and
determining whether the laws of nature are causally deterministic.
Some philosophers, known as Incompatibilists,
view determinism and free will as mutually
exclusive. If they believe in determinism, they will therefore
believe free will to be an illusion, a position known as Hard
Determinism. Proponents range from Baruch
Spinoza to Ted
Honderich.
Others, labeled Compatibilists
(or "Soft Determinists"), believe that the two ideas can be
coherently reconciled. Adherents of this view include Thomas
Hobbes and many modern philosophers.
Incompatibilists who accept free will but
reject determinism are called Libertarians,
a term not to be confused with the political sense. Robert Kane
is a modern defender of this theory.
It is a popular misconception that determinism
necessarily entails that humanity or individual humans have no
influence on the future and its events ( a position known as
Fatalism).
Determinists, however, believe that the level to which human beings
have influence over their future is itself dependent on present and
past.
Cosmology and cosmogony
Cosmology is the branch of metaphysics that deals with the world as the totality of all phenomena in space and time. Historically, it has had quite a broad scope, and in many cases was founded in religion. The ancient Greeks did not draw a distinction between this use and their model for the cosmos. However, in modern use it addresses questions about the Universe which are beyond the scope of physical science. It is distinguished from religious cosmology in that it approaches these questions using philosophical methods (e.g. dialectics). Cosmogony deals specifically with the origin of the universe.Modern metaphysical cosmology and cosmogony try
to address questions such as:
- What is the origin of the Universe? What is its first cause? Is its existence necessary? (see monism, pantheism, emanationism and creationism)
- What are the ultimate material components of the Universe? (see mechanism, dynamism, hylomorphism, atomism)
- What is the ultimate reason for the existence of the Universe? Does the cosmos have a purpose? (see teleology)
Criticism
Metaphysics has been attacked, at different times in history, as being futile and overly vague, or of no use entirely.David Hume
argued with his empiricist principle that all
knowledge involves either relations of ideas or matters of
fact:
Immanuel
Kant prescribed a limited role to the subject and argued
against knowledge progressing beyond the world of our
representations, except to knowledge that the noumena exist:
A.J.
Ayer is famous for leading a "revolt against metaphysics,"
where he claimed that its propositions were meaningless in his book
"Language, Truth and Logic". Ayer was a defender of
verifiability theory of meaning. British universities became
less concerned with the area for much of the mid 20th century.
However, metaphysics has seen a reemergence in recent times among
some philosophy departments due to the perceived failure of
verificationism.
Writers in so-called Continental
philosophy have often elaborated views against metaphysics.
Martin
Heidegger sees the history of western philosophy as being
constituted by "forgetfulness of Being" and calls this thought
"metaphysical". Such thought looks beyond beings towards their
ground (zum Grund), aiming at a fundamentam absolutum, such as the
Platonic Idea or the Kantian thing-in-itself, "Ding an sich". For
example, Descartes finds such a "fundamentam absolutum" through the
"ego cogito", the self-certain subject. This thinking construes the
world as object for this self-certain subject, but does not
question or evaluate its own presuppositions about the nature of
Being. For Heidegger, such thinking "forgets" the question of
Being, and sees this "forgetfulness" as symptomatic of metaphysical
thought, or of Western philosophy since Plato (but not
including Pre-Socratic_philosophy).
Jaques
Derrida could be said to continue, if tenuously, Heidegger's
project of "overcoming metaphysics". Crucially, metaphysics is seen
by both thinkers as something one cannot simply step outside of or
escape, since a rejection of this form is already in itself a
metaphysical maneuver. Heidegger conceives of a process of
"overcoming metaphysics" through, for example, what he calls Poetry
("Dichtung"), or "Thinking", or non-metaphysical "awareness of
Being".
Another view is that metaphysical statements are
not meaningless statements, but rather that they are generally not
fallible, testable or provable statements (see Karl Popper).
That is to say, there is no valid set of empirical observations nor
a valid set of logical arguments, which could definitively prove
metaphysical statements to be true or false. Hence, a metaphysical
statement usually implies an idea about the world or about the
universe, which may seem reasonable but is ultimately not
empirically verifiable. That idea could be changed in a
non-arbitrary way, based on experience or argument, yet there
exists no evidence or argument so compelling that it could
rationally force a change in that idea, in the sense of definitely
proving it false.
Disciplines, topics and problems
Notable metaphysicians and critics of metaphysics
See also
Further reading
- The London Philosophy Study Guide offers many suggestions on what to read, depending on the student's familiarity with the subject: Logic & Metaphysics
Notes and references
Bibliography
- Butchvarov, Panayot (1979). Being Qua Being: A Theory of Identity, Existence and Predication. Bloomington and London: Indiana University Press.
- Harris, E. E. (1965). The Foundations of Metaphysics in Science. London: George Allen and Unwin.
- Harris, E. E. (2000). The Restitution of Metaphysics. New York: Humanity Books.
- Kant, I (1781). Critique of Pure Reason.
- Gale, Richard M. (2002). The Blackwell Guide to Metaphysics. Oxford: Blackwell.
- Lowe, E. J. (2002). A Survey of Metaphysics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- Loux, M. J. (2006). Metaphysics: A Contemporary Introduction (3rd ed.). London: Routledge.
- Kim, J. and Ernest Sosa Ed. (1999). Metaphysics: An Anthology. Blackwell Philosophy Anthologies.
- Kim, J. and Ernest Sosa, Ed. (2000). A Companion to Metaphysics. Malden Massachusetts, Blackwell, Publishers.
External links
- Astral Society The Internet's Largest Metaphysical Community
- Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. "Metaphysics" (by Peter van Inwagen).
- Aristotle's Metaphysics trans. by W. D. Ross
- Aristotle's Metaphysics trans. by Hugh Tredennick (HTML at Perseus)
- Aristotle's Metaphysics at Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- Hume's Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding: Mirrored at eBooks@Adelaide
- E-text (The Norman Kemp Smith translation of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason)
- Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, entry under OBJECT, by Henry Laycock
- Metaphysics: Multiple Meanings A page that succinctly differentiates between various uses of the term "metaphysics."
- Ways of Seeing - A common sense exploration of modern metaphysics.
metaphysics in Afrikaans: Metafisika
metaphysics in Arabic: ميتافيزيقا
metaphysics in Azerbaijani: Metafizika
metaphysics in Bengali: অধিবিদ্যা
metaphysics in Min Nan: Hêng-jî-siōng-ha̍k
metaphysics in Belarusian (Tarashkevitsa):
Мэтафізыка
metaphysics in Bavarian: Metaphysik
metaphysics in Bosnian: Metafizika
metaphysics in Bulgarian: Метафизика
metaphysics in Catalan: Metafísica
metaphysics in Czech: Metafyzika
metaphysics in Danish: Metafysik
metaphysics in German: Metaphysik
metaphysics in Estonian: Metafüüsika
metaphysics in Modern Greek (1453-):
Μεταφυσική
metaphysics in Spanish: Metafísica
metaphysics in Esperanto: Metafiziko
metaphysics in Basque: Metafisika
metaphysics in Persian: متافیزیک
metaphysics in French: Métaphysique
metaphysics in Western Frisian: Metafysika
metaphysics in Galician: Metafísica
metaphysics in Classical Chinese: 形而上學
metaphysics in Hindi: तत्त्वमीमांसा
metaphysics in Croatian: Metafizika
metaphysics in Ido: Metafiziko
metaphysics in Indonesian: Metafisika
metaphysics in Icelandic: Frumspeki
metaphysics in Italian: Metafisica
metaphysics in Hebrew: מטאפיזיקה
metaphysics in Latin: Metaphysica
metaphysics in Luxembourgish: Metaphysik
metaphysics in Lithuanian: Metafizika
metaphysics in Hungarian: Metafizika
metaphysics in Macedonian: Метафизика
metaphysics in Malay (macrolanguage):
Metafizik
metaphysics in Mongolian: Метафизик
metaphysics in Dutch: Metafysica
metaphysics in Japanese: 形而上学
metaphysics in Norwegian: Metafysikk
metaphysics in Uzbek: Metafizika
metaphysics in Polish: Metafizyka
klasyczna
metaphysics in Portuguese: Metafísica
metaphysics in Romanian: Metafizică
metaphysics in Russian: Метафизика
metaphysics in Albanian: Metafizika
metaphysics in Sicilian: Mitafìsica
metaphysics in Simple English: Metaphysics
metaphysics in Slovak: Metafyzika
metaphysics in Slovenian: Metafizika
metaphysics in Serbian: Метафизика
metaphysics in Finnish: Metafysiikka
metaphysics in Swedish: Metafysik
metaphysics in Tagalog: Metapisika
metaphysics in Vietnamese: Siêu hình học
metaphysics in Turkish: Metafizik
metaphysics in Ukrainian: Метафізика
metaphysics in Urdu: مابعدالطبیعیات
metaphysics in Volapük: Metafüd
metaphysics in Contenese: 形而上學
metaphysics in Chinese: 形而上学
Synonyms, Antonyms and Related Words
aesthetics, axiology, casuistry, cosmology, epistemology, ethics, existentialism, first
philosophy, gnosiology, hyperphysics, logic, mental philosophy, moral
philosophy, ontology,
phenomenology,
philosophastry,
philosophic doctrine, philosophic system, philosophic theory,
philosophical inquiry, philosophical speculation, philosophy, school of
philosophy, school of thought, science of being, sophistry, the first
philosophy, theory of beauty, theory of knowledge, value
theory